Jill Buroker

 

The  unit  of  reasoning  is  called  an argument.    Another  term  for  an  argument  is  an
inference .    There  are  two  types  of  reasoning:    justificatory  and  explanatory.    Justificatory
reasoning  is  used  when  we  want  to  prove  a  conclusion,  or  show  that  it  is likely to be true.
Explanatory reasoning is used to explain why something is true.  In this course we are concerned
more with justificatory reasoning.

Official  definition:    An  argument  is  a  set  of  statements ,  some  of  which  are  offered  in
support of another.   The statement one is attempting to support is called the conclusion.  The
statement(s) offered in support of the conclusion are called the  premise(s).  Premises are offered
as reasons or evidence to take the conclusion t o be true.

What is a statement?  A statement   is a  sentence   that has a truth value,   that is, it is either
true or false.  The fact that it has a truth value does  not  imply that we know what that truth value
is.  Not all sentences have truth values.  Remem ber the grammatical classification of four types
of  sentences  –  declarative,  interrogative,  imperative,  and  exclamatory.    Which  types  do  not
typically have truth values?
Normally we make statements in the form of declarative sentences:  “God exists.”  “The
Earth has one natural satellite.”  “2 + 2 = 7.”  “It certainly is warm today.”  It is possible to
express a statement in other forms of sentence.  In particular, we sometimes express statements
in the form of questions, and imperatives can also be reworded as statements.  What do we call
questions which are used to make statements?

The  point  of  justificatory  reasoning  is  to  demonstrate  the  truth  of  a  conclusion,  by
offering  one  or  more  premises  in  its  support.    Here is an argument, presented in a standar d
format, with the premises given above the line, and the conclusion below the line:

1.  Everything that exists has a cause.
2.  The universe exists .
3.   Therefore, the universe has a cause.

The above argument has two premises.  Not all arguments have two p remises.  Here is another
argument, with only one premise:

1.   In a recent study, 66% of the people who took medication X had fewer colds.
2.   Therefore, over half of the population in general who take medication X will have
fewer colds.

Notice that the definition of an argument says only that one must offer  some  statement(s) in
support of the conclusion.  It does not say how many must be offered.  The only restriction is that
the number of statements must be finite.
When one makes a statement without  offering any supporting reason, one is not making
an argument.  A set of statements in which none are offered to support another therefore do not
constitute an argument.  The key to an argument (or inference) is  offering at least one statement
(premise) to accept ano ther statement as true.

Now, let’s see how much of this you understood.  Answer the following questions:
1.  How many statements, at a minimum, must an argument have?
2.  How many premises must there be in an argument?
3.  Why does the definition say that  the premises are “offered” in support of the conclusion,
rather than that the premises in fact support the conclusion?
2  22
Arguments can become very complex.  As we shall see, one can reason serially, using a
conclusion as support for a further conclusion.  The distinction between premise and conclusion
is  a  functional  distinction:    whether  a  statement  is  a  premise  or  conclusion  in  an  argument
depends solely on whether it is used to support another statement (thereby becoming a premise)
or whether one is offer ing statements to support it (thereby becoming a conclusion).  Thus the
same  statement  may  function  as  a  premise  in  one  argument  and  a  conclusion  in  another.
Consider this example:

1.  Everything that exists has a cause.
2.  The universe exists.
3.  Therefore, the universe has a cause.
4.  The cause of the universe could only be God.
5.  Therefore, God exists.
6.  Therefore, God must have a cause.  (By 1 and 5.)

Question:  how many arguments are there here?  We identify and individuate arguments
(or infe rences) by the conclusion.  Each inference to a conclusion counts as a  separate argument.
(We shall see when we evaluate arguments why this is so.)  So the answer is that there are three
arguments in the above example, arranged serially.  So look at state ments 3 and 5.  Are they
conclusions or premises or both?  Answer:  it depends on which inference you are talking about.
In the first inference, from statements 1 to 3, statements 1 and 2 are the premises, and statement
3 is the conclusion.  In the second   inference, from statements 3 to 5, statements 3 and 4 are
premises, and statement 5 is the conclusion.  Similarly, statements 5 and 1 are premises in the
third inference, where statement 6 is the conclusion.  Statements 3 and 5 are also called sub -conclusions, and statement 6 the final conclusion of the argument.

READ ALSO :   What do contemporary Iranian foreign and defence policies indicate about its grand strategy?

DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS

There are two types of justificatory reasoning:  deductive and inductive. They differ in
terms of their evidence and purpose.   Deductive arguments  are those in which one intends to
guarantee   the truth of the conclusion.  When one argues deductively, one offers premises or
evidence that one takes to provide sufficient justification to show that a conclusion must be true.
Here are some common forms of deductive reasoning:

1.  All humans are mortal.     1.  If Jill owns a Porsche, then she owns a car.
2.  Socrates is human.      2.  Jill owns a Porsche.
3.  Therefore, Socrates is mortal.  3.  Therefore, Jill owns a car.

In  inductive  reasoning  one  offers  premises  or  evide nce  to  provide  some  support   for  the
conclusion.  The best one can do in inductive reasoning is to demonstrate that a conclusion is
probable   or likely to be true .  This is because the premises offer  empirical evidence , or evidence
derived from experience or  observations.  In inductive arguments, the premises make claims
about observed cases, and draw conclusions about unobserved cases, as in the following:

1.   All swans observed so far are white.  1.  In the past, the sun has risen every day.
2.   Therefore, all swan s are white.     2.  In the future, the sun will rise every day.

Because  deductive  and  inductive  arguments  have  different  purposes  (related  to  the  different
types  of  evidence  they  offer),  there  are  different  methods  for  evaluating  them.    Put  briefly,
deducti ve  arguments  can  be  evaluated  for  validity  and  soundness.    By  contrast,  inductive
arguments  are  evaluated  in  terms  of  their  degree  of  strength.    Because  most  philosophical
arguments are deductive, we shall focus on the concepts of validity and soundness.
3  33
IDENTIFYING ARGUMENTS:    INFERENCE INDICATORS

Inference indicators are words or phrases used to indicate that someone is making an inference
(an argument).  Because inferences have two parts –  premises and conclusions  –  there are two
types of indicators.  In both cases the indicator  precedes  the statement it indicates as a premise or
a conclusion.  For example, this sentence has two statements, and one inference indicator:
“Because the final counts for 30% of your grade, you should study carefully for it.”
The indicator here is the word ‘Because’, which is a premise indicator.  This word indicates that
the first statement ‘the final counts for 30% of your grade’ is used as a premise to support the
statement ‘you should study carefully for it.’  The followin g sentence makes the same argument,
but uses a conclusion indicator instead of a premise indicator:
“The final counts for 30% of your grade, so you should study carefully for it.”
The same statement functions as a premise supporting the same conclusion.

Here are some common premise indicators:
Because…       since…(time exception)   for…(preposition exception)
as shown by…      as indicated by…     follows from…
assuming that…     for the reasons that…     in view of the fact that…
may be inferred /derived from…

Here ar e the most common conclusion Indicators:
Consequently…    Therefore…       So…
I conclude that…     proves that…      hence…
Which shows that…    must… (some exceptions)  implies that…
Entails that…      accordingly…       allows us to infer that…
Thus… (exceptions)    demonstrates that…     it follows that…

These  are  not  the  only  ways  to  indicate  premises  and  conclusions,  but  these  are  the  most
common.  You need to think about the meaning of the phrases preceding statements that might
be construed as reasons or conclusions.

Another  point  to  keep  in  mind  when  identifying  arguments  is  that  premises  and
conclusions can be stated in any order.  The brief argument given above can also be stated with
the conclusion given before the premise:  “You should study carefully for the final, si nce it
counts for 30% of your grade.”  So when you are reading for arguments, you have to identify the
premises and conclusions in terms of which statements offer support, and which statements are
being supported.

READ ALSO :   International HRM

Some reasoning contains NO inference i ndicators, e.g.:  “It’s going to rain.  You should
take  an  umbrella.”    To  decide  whether  discourse  contains  reasoning,  we  go  through  this
procedure:
1)  we look for inference indicators.  If we find them, we  must   analyze the reasoning
following the infere nce indicators (even if it is not good reasoning).
2)    if  there  are  no  inference  indicators,  we  follow  the  Principle  of  Charity.   The
Principle  of  Charity  says  that  you  must  interpret  the  passage  so  as  to  make  it  the strongest
reasoning possible .  This means:  If a passage has no inference indicators and there is no way to
interpret  it  as  containing  good  reasoning,  we  must  call  it  nonreasoning.    If  the  passage  has
inference  indicators  but  there  is  more  than  one  possible  interpretation,  we  must  choose  the
i nterpretation that results in the strongest reasoning.  Now why do we do this?

Remember:  the argument is in the speaker’s or writer’s intention.  If someone is offering
premises to support a conclusion, we must call it an argument, even if the reasoning is bad
reasoning.  Once you understand this point, you will be on the way to understanding the
nature of argument.
4  44

Argument identification exercises

Decide  which  of  the  following  passages  contain  arguments.    Be  able  to  defend  your
position.  For those that do, use inference indicators to determine which statements are premises
(reasons) and which are conclusions.  In some cases you may need to insert inference indicators
where they are reasonable.  You also may need to supply an implicit conclusion (one that is
logically implied but not actually stated).  Do your best.

1.  John would help us move, but he has a bad back.  So we are going to need to find someone
else.

2.  Men are better at lifting heavy furniture than women.

3.  She must have money.  Just look at the clothes she’s wearing.

4.  The nicotine in tobacco is addictive like heroin.  Therefore, tobacco should be treated as a
drug.

5.  Using threats of foreign trade sanctions as a device to punish nations that violate human
rights is a bad poli cy, for it does not change the behavior of the violators and only hurts our jobs
and trade.

6.  If Jones were the thief, he would have skipped town.  But he stayed around.  Can you see
what that says?

7.  Everybody has needs.  You don’t fill mine.  So I’ m splittin’.

8.  Don’t chew ice.  You may crack a tooth.

9.  She’s been married since last June.

10.  Heat the oil in a frying pan with a cover.  When hot, add the onion, ginger, garlic, and salt
and pepper to taste, and stir fry for 1 minute.  Add the  cauliflower and turn the pieces in the oil
in a gentle stir fry for 2 minutes.  Add vegetable broth, butter, and milk, and continue to stir fry
gently for 2 minutes, until the butter has melted and the liquid has coated the vegetable and is
boiling vigorously.

11.  Smoking endangers nonsmokers too.  It should be banned from buildings open to the public.

12.  The houses were covered with vines bearing bell-shaped flowers playing coloraturas.  The
guitars inside of the houses or on the doorsteps took up the   color chromatics and emitted sounds
which evoked the flavor of guava, papaya, cactus figs, anise, saffron, and red pepper.

13.   Neutron:  a neutral uncharged particle of atomic weight approximately unity….  Closely
packed neutrons and protons compose the  nuclei of all atoms.  The neutron is slightly heavier
than  the  proton;    in  the  free  state  it  decays,  yielding  a  proton,  with  a  half  life  of  about  12
minutes.  It has some magnetic properties.
5  55
EVALUATING DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS:  VALIDITY AND SOUNDNESS

When  we  evaluate  DEDUCTIVE  arguments,  we  are  trying  to  determine  whether  the
premises succeed in proving the truth of the conclusion.  (For inductive arguments, the premises
can supply weak to strong support, but cannot conclusively prove a conclusion.) A  succ essful
deductive argument is called a  sound argument .  To be sound, a deductive argument must pass
two tests: the  validity test  and the truth test.  These tests are independent of each other:  an
argument can pass both, or fail both, or pass one but not th e other.

READ ALSO :   Velma sue Bates v. Dura Automotive Systems, Inc.

1.  Deductive Validity:  has to do with the logical correctness or form of the argument,
with the degree of support the premises give the conclusion.  In testing for validity, we have to
decide  whether the conclusion follows logically from the premises.

2.   Truth:  has to do with the actual truth value of the premises   (NOTE:  only the
premises, not the conclusion).  In particular, we must decide whether all the premises of the
argument are in fact true (to the best of our ability).

If an ar gument flunks either test, then it is UNSOUND:

SOUNDNESS  =  DEDUCTIVE VALIDITY  +   TRUTH (of all the premises)

Terminology:  An argument is not true or false;  it is valid or invalid.  Individual statements in
the argument (premises and conclusion) are   true or false, but they are not valid or invalid.  The
statements are not sound or unsound, only a complete argument is sound or unsound.

Validity:    A  deductively  valid  argument  is  one  in  which, if  the  premises  were  true,  the
conclusion must be true.    ( Note that this does not say that the premises are in fact true.)  In
other words, if in evaluating an argument, we decide that even if the premises were true the
conclusion could still be false, then we have decided that the argument is invalid.

Here is a deductively valid  argument:  1.  If Sadie is a cat, then Sadie is a mammal.
2.  Sadie is a cat.
3.  Therefore, Sadie is a mammal.

Now does the validity of the argument depend on whether premises 1 and 2 are both true?  What
do you need to kno w to decide whether the argument is valid?  Sound?

What about this argument?  Is it valid?  Is it sound?  Defend your answers by reference to the
definitions.   1.  All elected politicians are liars.
2.  Clarence Thomas is an elected politician .
3.  The refore, Clarence Thomas is a liar.

What about this argument:  is it valid?  is it sound?
1.  Some roses are red.
2.  Some violets are blue .
3.  Therefore, interest rates will not rise this year.

In reading philosophy, when you encounter an argume nt, you should ask these questions:
Is it a valid argument;  that is, if the premises were true, would the conclusion have
to be true?
Are the premises in fact true (to the best of my knowledge)?  If I think the conclusion is
false, can I sa y which of the premises are false or explain why the argument is invalid?  Can I
defend my evaluation?
6  66

Homework

Evaluate  the  following  deductive  arguments  according  to  the  validity  and  truth  tests.    Say
whether they are valid or invalid, and sound or unsound .  Defend your answers.  If you cannot
decide on soundness, explain why .

Argument 1:

1.  Anyone who is in San Bernardino is in California.
2.  I (the student now doing this homework) am currently in California.
3.  Therefore, I (the student now doing this homework) am currently in San Bernardino.

Argument 2:

1.  All CSUSB professors are under the age of 29.
2.  Dr.  Nist  is a CSUSB professor.
3.  Therefore, Dr. Nist  is under the age of 29.

Argument 3:

1.   Barack Obama  is  currently President of the United States.
2.  Therefore, water  is composed of two molecules of hydrogen and one molecule of oxygen.

Argument 4:

1.  All trout are cats.
2.  All cats are fish.
3.  Therefore, all trout are fish.

Argument 5:

1.  If I own a Boeing 747, then I own an airplane.
2.  I don’t own a Boeing 747.
3.  Therefore, I don’t own an airplane.

Argument 6:

1.  If I own a Boeing 747, then I own an airplane.
2.  I don’t own an airplane.
3.  Therefore, I don’t own a Boeing 747.

PLACE THIS ORDER OR A SIMILAR ORDER WITH US TODAY AND GET AN AMAZING DISCOUNT 🙂